What Is Ontology? Why Should You Care That It Exists?

Ontology is one of those words that makes you sound very clever at dinner parties, right up until someone asks you what it means. Then, like Schrödinger’s cat, your confidence both exists and doesn’t exist simultaneously. But fear not! Today we unwrap the frosting on this dense philosophical treat.

The Basics: Defining Ontology

Ontology is the branch of philosophy concerned with the study of being, existence, and what there is. The term comes from the Greek words ontos (being) and logos (discourse or study), roughly translating to “the study of being.”

But ontology isn’t just about abstract daydreaming. It tries to answer some of the most fundamental questions humans can ask: What kinds of things exist? Do universals like “redness” exist independently of red objects? Is a chair still a chair if nobody’s sitting in it? And—perhaps most crucially—do holes exist, or are they just places where stuff isn’t?

A Brief History of Ontology

The ontological musings go all the way back to pre-Socratic philosophers like Parmenides, who boldly claimed that only being is, and that non-being is unthinkable. Heraclitus, ever the contrarian, emphasized becoming and change instead. This early bickering set the tone for the next two millennia of metaphysical squabbling.

Plato and Aristotle systematized ontology in Ancient Greece. Plato famously posited a world of eternal Forms—abstract entities like “Justice” or “Triangle”—which are more real than the messy approximations we encounter in daily life. Aristotle, ever the empiricist, thought categories like “substance” and “accident” were a better way to talk about what’s actually real in the world we observe.

In the medieval period, ontological debates became theological battlegrounds. Thinkers like Thomas Aquinas debated the ontological status of God and angels with all the gravity of someone negotiating a divine tax code.

Fast forward to the early modern period, and you’ll find thinkers like Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz refining ontological questions around substance, mind, and matter. But perhaps no one popularized the question of being more than Martin Heidegger, who opened his magnum opus Being and Time (1927) with a lament that people had forgotten to even ask what “being” means (Heidegger, 1962/2008).

Why It Matters

Ontology is foundational to many other branches of philosophy. Ethics assumes the existence of agents and actions. Epistemology assumes there are beliefs about something. Even physics, as abstract as it can be, relies on metaphysical assumptions about what kinds of entities are fundamental.

Moreover, modern discussions in artificial intelligence, data science, and cognitive science often rely on applied ontology—how we categorize and represent the world in formal systems. Even your phone’s contact list has an implicit ontology: it assumes you exist, that you have names for people, and that “Mom” is a valid entry, even if she still hasn’t figured out how to open attachments.

Enter Nominalism

One of ontology’s more persistent headaches is the debate over universals—properties like “redness,” “goodness,” or “cupcake-ness.” Do these things exist independently of the particular red, good, or cupcake-like things we experience?

Nominalism answers: nope.

Nominalists argue that universals don’t exist outside of the words we use. There is no “redness” floating in some Platonic ether; there are just red things, and our use of the word “red” is a convenient linguistic trick (Rodriguez-Pereyra, 2002).

This position rose to prominence in the late medieval period with figures like William of Ockham (of “Ockham’s Razor” fame), who thought multiplying entities beyond necessity was a recipe for metaphysical indigestion. In short: if we can explain everything using only particular things, why invent spooky abstract universals?

Today, nominalism remains influential in philosophy, linguistics, and even software design—where modeling entities and avoiding unnecessary abstractions is considered a virtue.

Concluding Crumbs

So the next time someone asks what ontology is, you can smile with frosting-coated wisdom and say: “It’s the study of what exists—and whether things like cupcakes, colors, and concepts are real, or just figments of our categorizing brains.”

And as it turns out, even deciding whether a cupcake with brain frosting exists is an ontological question.


Sources:

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Being and Time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Harper Perennial Modern Thought. (Original work published 1927)
  • Loux, M. J. (2006). Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. Routledge.
  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. Oxford University Press.
  • Hoffman, J. & Rosenkrantz, G. (1994). Substance: Its Nature and Existence. Routledge.

This article was generated with the assistance of AI.

Leave a Reply